6. Set Theory for the Natural Numbers -Order

Assignment: Study the material in 1.2 of the text.

Measurement by "Ordinality"

6.1 Definition:

A Set, $\QTR{Large}{S}$ is said to be partially ordered or a poset if there is a binary relation "$\QTR{Large}{\leq }$" defined on $\QTR{Large}{S}$ satisfying the following three properties

  1. For all MATH

  2. For all MATH and MATH

  3. For all MATH and MATH MATH It is (totally)ordered if it also satifiesMATH

  4. For all MATH or MATH

 

6.2 Definition:

Given a partially ordered set $\QTR{Large}{S}$, we call MATH a chain of $\QTR{Large}{S}$ if it is totally ordered.

 

6.3 Lemma:

Let MATH . It is a simple matter to check that any a partial/total order on $\QTR{Large}{S}$, restricts to a partial/total order on $\QTR{Large}{T}$.

Proof: Verify for yourself.

 

6.4 Definition:

Given partially ordered sets MATH and $\QTR{Large}{C}$ , a one to one onto map MATH MATH MATH is called an order isomorphism if

MATH for all MATH

 

6.4.1 Lemma:Let MATH be ordered and MATH be a poset. Suppose we are given a one to one onto map MATH MATH MATH such that MATH for all MATHthen:

1. MATH is ordered

2. MATH is an order isomorphism.

3.If MATH is Well Ordered so is MATH

Proof:

1. Let MATH and MATH be such that MATH and MATH

Since MATH is ordered MATH or MATH and thus MATH or MATH

2. We need only show that for all MATH . Since MATH is ordered MATH or MATH

But MATH and by hypothesis MATH so MATH and, $\QTR{Large}{f\ }$since is one to one, $\QTR{Large}{a=b.}$

Thus we have MATH

3. Let MATH . Since MATH is Well Ordered let $\QTR{Large}{l}$ be the least element of MATH

Check that $\QTR{Large}{f(l)}$ is the least element of $\QTR{Large}{A.}$

 

Examples:

6.5 Definition:

Let $\QTR{Large}{S}$ be Ordered. Let MATHDefine, MATH , called the segment defined by $\QTR{Large}{a}$ as follows.

MATH

If MATHis finite it will be convenient to use the notation MATH for the number of member in $\QTR{Large}{S(a)}$ .

Example: In MATH with the usual ordering $\QTR{Large}{S(}$n$\QTR{Large}{)=n-1}$ and $\QTR{Large}{|S(}$nMATHn-1.



Well Ordered Sets

6.6 Definition: A Set, $\QTR{Large}{S}$ is said to be Well Ordered (WO) if it is Ordered and every subset MATH has a least member. That is there exists an MATH such that for all MATH MATH. Note that by 6.1.2. above, we know that $\QTR{Large}{l}$ is unique.

It is enough to assume that $\QTR{Large}{S}$ is partially ordered and every subset has a least element?

Any subset of a Well Ordered Set is Well Ordered, using the same order.Why?

Examples:

Assignment: Due Feb. 9: Show that any two orderings of a given finite set are order isomorphic.

6.7 Theorem:

Suppose that we have a proposition MATHn$\QTR{Large}{)}$ .

Suppose MATH1$\QTR{Large}{)}$ is true

and

for all nMATH, MATHnMATHn$\QTR{Large}{+}$1$\QTR{Large}{)}$ is true .

Then,

for all nMATHn$\QTR{Large}{)}$ is true .

Proof:

Let MATH be the set of all n for which MATHn$\QTR{Large}{)}$ is not true. Suppose $\QTR{Large}{B}$ were not empty. Then it has a least element, l . Since MATH1$\QTR{Large}{)}$ is true, l $\QTR{Large}{>\ }$1. We know that MATHl $\QTR{Large}{-\ }$1$\QTR{Large}{)}$ is true. But MATHl $\QTR{Large}{-\ }$1MATHl$\QTR{Large}{).}$Therefore MATHl$\QTR{Large}{)}$ is true. Hence $\QTR{Large}{B}$ is empty.


6.8 Theorem:

a. Given MATH , for any MATH , $\QTR{Large}{S(a)}$ is finite.

Moreover,

b. either $\QTR{Large}{S\ }$is finite or for any integer n $\QTR{Large}{\geq }$ 0 we can find a unique MATHwith MATHn.

Hence.

c. There exists an order isomorphism MATH

Proof:

a. Is immediate from the observation that since MATH , $\QTR{Large}{S(a)}$ is a subset of the segment of $\QTR{Large}{a}$ in MATH , which is finite.

b. Is a simple induction argument. Let MATH to be the least element of $\QTR{Large}{S.}$

Since MATH we have MATH0 . Moreover uniqueness follows from the fact that MATH for any MATHand MATH

Hence MATH1.

Assume that for 0 $\QTR{Large}{\leq }$ i MATHn we can find a unique MATHwith MATHi.

Since by assumption $\QTR{Large}{S}$ is not finite, let MATH be the least element of MATH

We need to verify that MATH

MATH,

hence MATHn+1.

First note that MATH, since if MATHthen MATH

So MATH

On the other hand if MATH

and MATH then MATH . thus MATH

Again uniqueness follow from the fact that since MATH for any

MATHand MATH we conclude that

MATH

we can now apply the principal of mathematical induction.

c. follows from b.

First define MATH by the formula $\QTR{Large}{h(}$nMATH

Clearly $\QTR{Large}{h}$ is one to one. If it were not onto let MATH and MATH

Suppose MATHm. Then MATH contradicting the uniqueness of MATH

Finally, let $\QTR{Large}{f=hg}$ where MATH is defined by the formula $\QTR{Large}{h(}$nMATHn-1

6.9 Theorem:

Let MATH MATH MATH be an order isomorphism. . Then

1. for all MATH MATH

2. if MATH (or MATH) is Well Ordered

so is MATH (or MATH)

Assignment: Due Feb. 9: Prove this

Solution: See 6.4.1 above.

Example:

Assignment: Due Feb. 9: Show that

1. There exist a one to one onto set map$\QTR{Large}{.}$

2. MATH is a Well Ordering

3. MATH is not order isomorphic to MATH with the usual ordering.

(Hint:) Use 6.8 and 6.9 to prove 3.


Solution: We give the details for 3.

Let MATH be an order isomorphism. Suppose $\QTR{Large}{f(}$nMATH By 6.9.3 $\QTR{Large}{f(S(}$nMATH ,which is not possible since $\QTR{Large}{S(}$n$\QTR{Large}{)}$ contains a finite number of elements and MATH does not.


Finally, we gather results above to state the following theorem, which characterizes Set Theory for the Natural Numbers.

6.10 Theorem:

For any MATH

1. There exists an n and an order isomorphism MATH

or

2. There exists an order isomorphism MATH


Examples:

While MATH the set of fractions greater than 0, is not well ordered by the usual ordering, it is not hard to put a non-standard well ordering on MATH .

Referring back to Page 0, consider the function MATH2MATH3MATHCheck that this is 1 to 1, hence MATH inherits a well ordering from MATH. This is certainly not the usual ordering since MATH12 and MATH108. hence 2$\QTR{Large}{\leq }$(MATH). Note as well that MATH inherits a form of mathematical induction from this well ordering albeit not a particularly useful one.